Habermas and the Idea of a Radical Democracy

Clotilde Nouët is an Assistant Professor in social and political philosophy at the University Mohammed VI Polytechnique in Rabat, Morocco, and a researcher at the Institut de Recherches Philosophiques de Lyon (IRPhiL) at the University of Lyon 3.

She devoted her doctoral dissertation to the philosophy of Jürgen Habermas, notably from the perspective of his relation to Marx and the Frankfurt School, trying to understand the interest of the modern concept of “public space” for a critical theory of democracy.

 

This interview was conducted by Luc Foisneau, in Paris, at the EHESS Audiovisual Center, 96 boulevard Raspail, on January 14, 2019.

Edited by Serge Blerald

Habermas today

Luc Foisneau: Hello Clotilde Nouët, thank you for accepting this interview before your intervention in the CESPRA normative political philosophy seminar. You worked on Habermas in the context of a PhD which you recently completed and you are currently interested in the questions raised by freedom of expression. Before coming to these questions, could you situate Habermas in the contemporary philosophical debate and perhaps, more specifically, give us the reasons for the interest of philosophers today in his ideas and philosophy?

 

Clotilde Nouët: Hello, and thank you very much for this invitation. I would say that we are currently witnessing in France a renewed interest in Habermasian thought, as well as an increased concern for rigor in the approach to his philosophy. For a long time, Habermas was referred to in an imprecise way as the “philosopher of consensus” or the “philosopher of communication”. However, it seems to me that in recent years — starting with the early works of Stéphane Haber1 and continuing with those of Alexandre Dupeyrix2, Isabelle Aubert3 and Jean-Marc Durand-Gasselin4 —there has been a real desire to read Habermas. And reading Habermas is a challenge, since he has published numerous articles and books, and since his thinking has evolved over time, drawing on a large number of authors and a permanent dialogue with different traditions. There was the Marxist tradition, first of all, especially that of the Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School, and then, from the 1990s, the Anglo-Saxon political philosophy, especially that of Rawls5.

Public Space and Democracy

Clotilde Nouët: It seems to me that one of the essential motives of the Habermasian thought, which is of interest to those working today on the theories of democracy, is the motive of the public space. This was the object of my thesis: to show that there is in his work the central intuition that the public space—in German, Öffentlichkeit, which literally means “publicity”—constitutes a fundamental feature of modern and contemporary democratic societies. This concept, whose study was inaugurated in Habermas’s habilitation thesis6, seems to me to offer a good entry point into his thought. And from there, its subsequent developments can be pursued through the various avatars of a general reflection on public space: the theory of language7 and communicational action8, the ethics of discussion9 and the theory of deliberative politics10.

Luc Foisneau: Concerning this question of public space, why is it important? Why is it that modernity, as Habermas re-reads it, is characterized by the emergence of a public space? What does this say about modern politics? Could you, in order to establish a link between these different problems, clarify Habermas’ reading of modernity?

 

Clotilde Nouët: In his habilitation thesis, which was published in 1962, Habermas was interested in showing that the public space emerges from a certain form of sociability and a certain type of discursive practice that the bourgeoisie makes use of within social spaces such as the café, the salon (although this was originally a rather aristocratic space), or other forms of spontaneous exchange. Habermas sees in these practices the emergence of a rather peculiar subjectivity, which is initially part of a literary criticism. He is interested in the fact that the exercise of judgment of taste is being politicized, particularly at the time of revolutions, and studies how the public space will gradually form an intermediate zone in which members of civil society will be able to constitute themselves as a political community. For him, this is both the reflexive and constitutive role of the public space in modernity.

Luc Foisneau: What is the relationship between this practice or these discursive practices—you insist on their plurality —and the revolutionary phenomenon? In what way does the revolution take up these practices; in what way does it transform them? How do you read this in the light of your work on Habermas?

 

Clotilde Nouët: In his habilitation thesis, Habermas insists on the fact that the revolution takes hold of the critical dimension of public space: the capacity of members of civil society to constitute themselves into a collective body produces a critique of absolutist power, because it requires for the State reason to be subjected to the exercise of a collective practical reason. It is this critical dimension, which, according to him, is the springboard for an indefinite politicization of civil society and its claim to exist as an autonomous instance from the State.

Luc Foisneau: Why do you say “indefinite”? One could imagine that once deliberative representative institutions have been put in place, the practice of criticism would take on forms that are different from revolutionary forms. What is Habermas’ position on the articulation between forms of critical discursivity within political institutions and the intervention of the people in the streets?

 

Clotilde Nouët: This idea of an indefinite politicization is a central aspect: the critical process set in motion with the raise of public opinion can indeed produce institutions —deliberation then takes place in formal instances, for example in parliaments. But radical democracy is found where an anarchic public space remains, which is likely to challenge institutions. Habermas therefore proposes a model with a double trigger, consisting both in a parliamentary pole, and an extra-institutional pole. He uses Hannah Arendt’s idea of power to think a constituent communicational power that persists outside representative democracy11, and which the latter cannot absorb.

Luc Foisneau: Is it desirable that representative and deliberative democracy can absorb this remainder? Or is this anarchic public space, this residue that cannot be assimilated by representative democracy, constitutive of democracy for Habermas? If it were, would it not constitute a limit to Habermas's communicational democracy, since organized communication constitutes the horizon of democratic practice there? In other words, what relationship do you see between deliberative democracy and radical democracy?

 

Clotilde Nouët: It seems to me that the very concept of democracy points to a fundamental inadequacy between the political people and what we might call its sociological figures. Hence, there is a permanent tension between the institutions that aim to represent the people and the manifestations of a surplus that cannot be assimilated by representation. This is why the existence of a public space outside the institutional public space is a specificity that is properly democratic. But this does not go without raising difficulties: first of all, the question of its legitimacy, but also difficulties linked to the modalities of construction of such an extra-institutional space, notably by bodies that escape the control of the political actors themselves. This space is taken over by the media, which contribute to its public visibility, but which can also play a significant role in the formulation of problems. Deliberative arenas do not always have the spontaneous and self-piloted character they should have. Not to mention the function of legitimizing public opinion in the context of welfare states, which Habermas showed in the 1970s to be particularly affected by legitimation crises12.

Freedom of Speech

Luc Foisneau: This distinction is indeed very important. We can see that it is at the heart of the current debate: there is growing suspicion about the public space that is being covered by the media, and this questioning is not without impact on the way in which we conceive of the constitutional right to freedom of expression. Could you clarify how you understand the extension and limits of freedom of expression within the current political context, which is characterized by a tension between an official public space and an anarchic public space, a tension that is expressed on social networks, on traffic circles, in cafés, wherever political discussion takes place?

 

Clotilde Nouët: Perhaps we should start by trying to clarify what we mean by freedom of expression. The classical liberal interpretation tends to see it as a sphere of individual expression protected from state interference. But Habermas conceives of freedom of expression rather as one of the constituent rights of the public sphere, alongside freedom of assembly and association and freedom of the press. The idea is that freedom of expression is one of the cornerstones of a democratic public space, and therefore contributes in an essential way to democracy itself: far from being a negative freedom, or to use the terminology developed by Hohfeld, a privilege13, a simple freedom to do something without being prevented from doing it, it is therefore both a positive and political freedom, which may require a “guarantee of participation14”, and which is part of a collective exercise of expression.

Luc Foisneau: What exactly is meant by this astonishing formulation, in view of classical liberalism, according to which freedom of expression would be a social right?

 

Clotilde Nouët: Habermas himself does not use this expression. But I rely on a 1963 text in which he rereads the Declarations of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, trying to distance himself from the Marxist reading of human rights15. He shows that the object of Marx’s criticism, namely rights according to political liberalism, can be thought of differently: these rights are in fact ways of articulating social demands. It is thus a very specific architecture of the relations between civil society and the State that is put in place on the occasion of the Declarations of Rights. These should not be understood as the manifestation of an opposition between individuals and the State. The determination of individual liberties reveals a certain relationship between civil society and the State. This interpretation clearly shows that what is at stake in the right to freedom of expression is the question of the social conditions for the exercise of this right. Thus, freedom of expression is not only a right to communicate and receive opinions, but a right to have access to spaces of expression where individual opinion is audible, as well as a right to dispose of a plurality of information and opinions allowing for a considered judgment to be formed. This necessarily leads us to reflect on the positive obligations of states or governments to ensure such a “claim-right”.

Luc Foisneau: What does this mean concretely in relation to the current situation? On the one hand, we have an official public space and media, which strongly frame freedom of expression, and, on the other hand, an anarchic public space in the strong sense of the term, where social demands are expressed that do not find an echo in the sphere of representation and official deliberation, as well as hate speech. This is one of the difficulties of the current situation16: do people seek to express a social situation that the rulers refuse to see, or to express opinions that the constitution forbids them to express because they are contrary to the spirit of the Republic? Can a Habermasian theory of the public space allow us to separate the wheat from the chaff —this formulation expresses, I am aware, a normative position —or, at least, guide us in the work of regulating this multiple expression?

 

Clotilde Nouët: Habermas would probably not help us to establish a normative dividing line between good and bad discourse, because the procedural model of democracy that he defends does not claim to impose normative content on discussions. The latter are supposed to regulate themselves and produce their own normativity.  This being said, there are two scenarios. Deliberations that are subject to procedural constraints, as reflected in a constitutional framework, are subject to norms that could be called “of equal freedom” and that imply mutual respect in deliberation. Moreover, such deliberations are not necessarily the monopoly of institutions. On the other hand, what Habermas calls “mass communication” refers to all the flows of opinions and ideas that circulate in the media space (and today we would include social networks), which, for their part, do not always seek representativeness or quality. But this is due to the very structure of such communication, which escapes face-to-face encounters —therefore to the reversibility of the positions of the speaker and the recipient —and thus can emancipate itself from the constraints of justification that normally weigh on deliberations. And yet Habermas does not call for the regulation of such communications. He is convinced that thoughtful public opinions are quite capable of being formed by exploiting the rational potential of so-called “wild” communication flows —as long as both press freedom and the diversity and independence of the media are guaranteed17.

Difficulties in Habermas’ thinking

Luc Foisneau: That’s the difficulty. Today, the French government has proposed a major national debate to respond to the multiple demands expressed in the Yellow jackets movement. The question is not simply who will lead or organize this debate, but whether the very framework of a national debate does not already constitute a radical limitation on the freedom to express oneself. The normative framework itself can raise suspicion, in the sense that the place where the debate is organized can in part determine the possibilities of expression. Could you tell us what the transformation of an anarchic debate into an official debate changes, or does not change, to the content of what is expressed? Can Habermas help us answer this question? Or maybe not? I am referring here to the critical dimension in your current reflection on his work.

 

Clotilde Nouët: Yes, from my point of view, the weaknesses of the Habermasian thought lie in the gap between its inaugural project and its realization. His project is indeed, through a theory of communication, to think the dissolution of all forms of domination, both social and political. The limit seems to me to lie less at the level of the idea of deliberative politics —which is a central concept to articulate different forms of political claims or political subjectivities —than at the level of the theory of discursive rationality, that is to say, at the level of the theory of argumentation that grounds the Habermasian conception of deliberative democracy.

Habermas is not sensitive enough, in my opinion, to the disqualifying effects of discourse that manifest themselves in the social space, whether these disqualifications are due to the difference in status between speakers or whether they are related to the fact that certain arguments used by political subjects are not always audible. Habermas’ idea is that, in principle if not in fact, the best argument will always win. We can maintain this regulatory ideal, but it is not enough to say that the discussion is likely to produce false statements. We still need to elucidate the reasons why it does so. This fallibility stems from the fact that one can argue in a supposedly rational space, which nevertheless remains impervious to the correctness of certain arguments because the structure of the social space masks the power relations that underlie the discussion. Let’s take the example of domestic violence: in order for this theme to be treated as a political theme, it is necessary to have previously accepted that the domestic sphere is not strictly a private space, so it is necessary to accept the idea of a relative politicization of the domestic sphere. This process implies, upstream of the rational space, that social relations or the whole social structure allow such arguments to be heard for what they are.

Unfold notes and references
Retour vers la note de texte 9736

1

Stéphane Haber, Habermas et la sociologie, Paris, Presses universitaires de France, 1998.

Retour vers la note de texte 9737

2

Alexandre Dupeyrix, Habermas. Citoyenneté et responsabilité, Paris, Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’homme, 2012.

Retour vers la note de texte 9738

3

Isabelle Aubert, Habermas. Une théorie critique de la société, Paris, CNRS Éditions, 2015.

Retour vers la note de texte 9739

4

Jean-Marc Durand-Gasselin, Le puzzle postmétaphysique de Habermas. La trajectoire philosophique de la Théorie de l’agir communicationnel, Bruxelles, La Lettre Volée, 2016.

Retour vers la note de texte 9740

5

Jürgen Habermas, “Reconciliation through the Public Use of Reason: Remarks on John Rawls’ Political Liberalism ”, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92, no. 3, 1995, pp. 109–131 ; John Rawls, “Political Liberalism: Reply to Habermas ”, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 92, no. 3, 1995, pp. 132–180.

Retour vers la note de texte 9741

6

J. Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Enquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society, Engl. Transl. T. Burger and F. Lawrence, Cambridge, Polity, 1989.

Retour vers la note de texte 9742

7

J. Habermas, On the Logic of the Social Sciences, Engl. Transl. S.W. Nicholsen and J.A. Stark, Cambridge (Mass.), The MIT Press, 1988.

Retour vers la note de texte 9743

8

J. Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, Eng. Transl. T. McCarthy, Boston, Mass., Beacon Press, Vol. 1, 1984; Vol. 2, 1987. 

Retour vers la note de texte 9744

9

J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Engl. Transl. C. Lenhardt and S. W. Nicholsen, Cambridge, Mass., The MIT Press, 1990.

Retour vers la note de texte 9745

10

J. Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, Engl. Transl. W. Rehg, Cambridge, Mass., The MIT Press, 1996.

Retour vers la note de texte 9746

11

J. Habermas, “Hannah Arendt’s Communications Concept of Power”, Social Research, vol. 44, no. 1, 1977, pp. 3–24.

Retour vers la note de texte 9747

12

J. Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, Engl. Transl. T. McCarthy, Boston, Beacon Press, 1975.

Retour vers la note de texte 9748

13

Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, “Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning”, The Yale Law Journal, vol. 26, no. 8, 1917, p. 710-770.

Retour vers la note de texte 9749

14

He borrows this term from the German constitutionalist and professor of public law Helmut Ridder, “Meinungsfreiheit,” in Neumann/Bettermann/Scheuner (ed.), Die Grundrechte, Vol. 2, Berlin, 1954.

Retour vers la note de texte 9750

15

J. Habermas, “Natural Law and Revolution” [1963], in Id., Theory and Practice, Engl. Transl. J. Viertel, Bacon, Beacon Press, 1973.

Retour vers la note de texte 9751

16

This interview was conducted during the Yellow jackets movement (gilets jaunes).

Retour vers la note de texte 9752

17

J. Habermas, “Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empirical Research”, Communication Theory, 16, p. 411-426.